Patheos Watermark

You are running a very outdated version of Internet Explorer. Patheos and most other websites will not display properly on this version. To better enjoy Patheos and your overall web experience, consider upgrading to the current version of Internet Explorer. Find more information HERE.

Religion Library: Confucianism

Sacred Time

Written by: Jeffrey Richey

As Kongzi stated that ultimate reality is beyond human comprehension, there is no sense of sacred time outside of ordinary time. Kongzi was a great supporter of li (ritual), as he felt that ritual solidified human social bonds; thus, in a sense, ritual sacralized ordinary time and daily life.

For Kongzi, rigorous attention to li provides a kind of self-replicating blueprint not only for good manners and taste, but also for personal morality and social order:

Do not look at, do not listen to, do not speak of, do not do whatever is contrary to ritual (Lunyu 12:1).

Appropriately quoting a poem from the Shijing, being the perfect guest or host, and correctly performing a public ceremony all are ritual actions, and all serve a common end: they regulate and maintain order. The nature of this order is threefold: aesthetic, moral, and social. It is aesthetic -- quoting the Shijing upholds the cultural hegemony of Zhou literature and the conventions of elite good taste. Moreover, it is moral -- good manners demonstrate both concern for others and a sense of one's place. Finally, it is social -- rituals properly performed duplicate ideal hierarchies of power, whether between ruler and subject, parent and child, or husband and wife. For Kongzi, the paramount example of harmonious social order seems to be xiao (filial piety), of which jing (reverence) is the key quality:  

Observe what a person has in mind to do when his father is alive, and then observe what he does when his father is dead. If, for three years, he makes no changes to his father's ways, he can be said to be a good son (Lunyu 1:11).

[The disciple] Ziyu asked about filial piety. [Kongzi] said, "Nowadays, for a person to be filial means no more than that he is able to provide his parents with food. Even dogs and horses are provided with food. If a person shows no reverence, where is the difference?" (Lunyu 2:7)

In serving your father and mother, you ought to dissuade them from doing wrong in the gentlest way. If you see your advice being ignored, you should not become disobedient but should remain reverent. You should not complain even if you are distressed. (Lunyu 4:18)

Paragon of filial piety: Public DomainThe character of this threefold order is deeper than mere conventions such as taste and decorum, as the above quotations demonstrate. Labeling it "aesthetic" might appear to demean or trivialize it, but to draw this conclusion is to fail to reflect on the peculiar way in which many Western thinkers tend to devalue the aesthetic. In Thinking Through Confucius (SUNY Press 1987), David Hall and Roger Ames argue that this "aesthetic" Confucian order is understood to be both intrinsically moral and profoundly harmonious, whether for one's own household, the court of one's king, or the cosmos at large. When persons and things are in their proper places -- and here tradition is the measure of propriety -- relations are smooth, operations are effortless, and the good is sought and done voluntarily. In the hierarchical political and social conception of Kongzi (and all traditional Chinese thinkers), what is below takes its cues from what is above. A moral ruler will diffuse morality to those under his sway; a moral parent will raise a moral child:

Let the ruler be a ruler, the subject a subject, a father a father, and a son a son (Lunyu 12:11).

Direct the people with moral force and regulate them with ritual, and they will possess shame, and moreover, they will be righteous (Lunyu 2:3).

 

Recommended Products


CLOSE | X

HIDE | X