On Lying: A Moral Guide Based Upon Lombard’s Sentences. Part IV: The Secondary Classification

On Lying: A Moral Guide Based Upon Lombard’s Sentences. Part IV: The Secondary Classification March 4, 2009

Part I

Part II
Part III

Having broken down lies into three different kinds, Lombard returns once again to their classification, and presents a different approach, using Augustine’s On Lying to show eight different types: “For first to be eschewed is that capital lie and far to be fled from, which is done in doctrine of religion; to which lie a man ought by no consideration to be induced. The second, that he should hurt some man unjustly: which is such that it profits no man and hurts some man. The third, which so profits one as to hurt another, but not in corporal defilement. The fourth, that which is done through only lust of lying and deceiving, which is an unmixed lie. The fifth, what is done with desire of pleasing by agreeableness in talk. All these being utterly eschewed and rejected, there follows a sixth sort which at once hurts nobody and helps somebody; as when, if a person’s money is to be unjustly taken from him, one who knows where the money is, should say that he does not know, by whomsoever the question be put. The seventh, which hurts none and profits some: except if a judge interrogate: as when, not wishing to betray a man who is sought for to be put to death, one should lie; not only a just and innocent, but also a culprit; because it belongs to Christian discipline neither to despair of any man’s amendment, nor to bar the way of repentance against any. Of which two sorts, which are wont to be attended with great controversy, we have sufficiently treated, and have shown what was our judgment; that by taking the consequences, which are honorably and bravely borne, these kinds also should be eschewed by brave and faithful and truthful men and women. The eighth sort of lie is that which hurts no man, and does good in the preserving somebody from corporal defilement, at least that defilement which we have mentioned above.[1] 

This list has ordered the lies according to how bad they are, with the first being the worst, and the eighth being of the least concern;[2] however, one should flee all, because each kind involves sin, and all sin stands in opposition to God.  Or, as Lombard quotes from Rufinus, “no lie is of God.”[3] What are we to make of this list? Lombard does not go into any detail, and so leaves it up for us to explore what was presented on our own.

Willful deception in regards to religion is said to be the worst, and most dangerous, kind of lie. Obviously this is because it is slander against God, who, more than even our neighbor, deserves our love. A lie against God, or the truths of God’s revelation, clearly breaks us away from the love we should have for God. Who could ever purposefully misrepresent their loved one? Love seeks to glorify the beloved. Tying to denigrate God can only be an act of blasphemy. Why would one go about such an act, and besmear God’s dignity? Either they think they have something to gain out of it (as happens when false prophets convince people to become their followers), or, they are filled with such hate, that they want to see others led astray and damned; obviously it is possible that the liar could have both of these objectives in mind at once.[4] In this way, a religious lie must be seen as a sin against both God and man, a sin against the whole of the law, because both fail to receive the love required of us. However, we must not confuse a lie about God, which is a great evil, with a mistaken view about him; presenting the second to others, though dangerous, is not intended as deceit and qualifies as a different kind of error.

The second is a lie which helps no one, told without any good intention whatsoever, and its only purpose is to deceive someone else so as to cause them injury. It is done out of pure malice. The reason why someone would tell such a lie is that they get some sort of inordinate pleasure from it.[5] It’s a strong violation against caritas, clearly indicating its objective gravity.

The third is nearly as bad as the second, because malice is clearly part of the intent, although, because the end result is that some small good comes out of it, that someone profits from it (beyond the pleasure the liar has in telling the lie), that good, however much is involved, mediates the objective evil involved.[6] Whatever the good is, and whatever caritas the liar might show to someone by lying in this manner, it is undermined by the overall malice intended in the act. As no ends can be used to justify the means, so in this case, no one can willfully lie about one person, harming them, to help someone else. The objective evil, because of the malice involved, remains significant.

The fourth type is the lie which is told by someone who lies, not out of malice, nor for any proper good, but because they have made a habit out of lying.[7] This kind of liar enjoys the act of lying itself, and finds a sense of pleasure in the execution of a lie. It is in this regard a lust, because it is desire for an inordinate pleasure, and it is one which leads the liar astray, away from the truth, though, because no direct malice is intended, and because the liar has become a habitual liar, the subjective guilt involved will be mediated. The objective guilt associated with the lie will depend upon what the lie actually is, though it will not be as grave as those lies done with direct, willful intent to harm someone. This is why it is listed after all lies associated with malice, even though one such lie (the third) is associated with some positive good, and this one is not.

The last four kinds of lies, while they are indeed sinful, are of minor significance in comparison of the first four. One might think the fourth itself is minor, because the subjective guilt would itself be minor, but, because it is only said by one who is in the habit of sinning, it indicates a dangerous position for a person to be in; they have created for themselves an addiction which they must struggle against and defeat, either now or through purgatory, for the good of their soul, otherwise it will lead them further astray into more objective evil.[8] What the last four have in common is that the lie is said, not out of malice, nor out of habit, but out of either a sense of pleasure that one thinks the lie will produce, or for the good they think such a lie will produce. We continue to see, in their classification, the sliding scale of evil, based upon the kind and amount of good produced from such lie, but, because no evil can be justified by the good which comes out of it, we must always remember that there still is a sin which must be atoned for when one tells one of these kinds of lies.[9]

Thus, we have for the fifth kind of lie, one which is done, not out of any ill will, but for the sake of pleasing someone, even if it would be better if nothing, or the truth, be said. This would be where white laws would be classified in this list. We often say something which we think someone else wants to hear, whether or not it is true, either because we think it would flatter them, or worse, we fear of what they might think or do if confronted with the truth. Because there is a deliberate intent to deceive, caritas has been breached, and the sinfulness of the act is established. Moreover, telling this kind of lie amounts to little objective harm, and little objective good, making it worse than the last three, which have true objective goods in mind.

The sixth, seventh, and eighth kind of lie are very similar, since they all seek to do some significant good, with the type of good involved indicating where the lie is to be placed upon Augustine’s scale. The least possible good would be done when one lies to protect someone from being unjustly taken advantage of, such as by protecting them from unjust search and seizure, while Augustine would have the seventh type of lie being found with one who lies in order to save someone’s life (whether or not they are an innocent person, because a Christian should hope that even the worst of criminals would be converted and change their ways), with the least sin being done when one lies in order to protect a person from undignified bodily harm. In each situation, there not only is the intent to deceive, but the actual attempt (whether or not it is successful), and so, the act would remain a lie, even if one were to say the person who was being lied to had no right to know what it is that they are being lied about. It would be worthwhile to note that we might want to reverse the order of the seventh and eighth sins from how Augustine placed them. For it would appear that one’s fundamental dignity is greater harmed by the taking of their life, their most fundamental treasure, than by causing bodily harm. This would be especially true when discussing lies told to protect someone from death. For what is it that would lead to that person’s death, but some assault on their body which would lead to their death? In this way, protecting someone from death would appear to include protecting them from bodily harm, but the reverse is not always true. Nonetheless, it is probable that Augustine is thinking of some great disfigurement which would, in life, be so unbearable, so undignified, that their fate might be seen as one which is “worse than death,” if it is at all possible.[10] 

Before moving on to the next chapter of The Sentences, it is worthwhile to note that St Thomas Aquinas, following Aristotle, presented a third way to classify lies: “On this way, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. iv, 7), lies are of two kinds, namely, the lie which goes beyond the truth, and this belongs to ‘boasting,’ and the lie which stops short of the truth, and this belongs to ‘irony.[11] This distinction is important, because it reminds us that lies can be told in half-truths, where we lie by stopping short of the truth, leading our audience to believe something erroneous, though if they had been told more, they would not be misled. Both of these forms of lies can be, and should be, seen as applicable to the three-fold and eight-fold distinctions Lombard presented to us; that one could lie in either fashion, by exaggeration or by half-truth, while following the patterns Lombard established. Aquinas points out that the two-fold classification is according to the essence of the lie, the three-fold distinction is according to their “nature as sins“, and relates to “those things that aggravate or diminish the sin of lying on the part of the intended,” and the eight-fold distinction classifies in a “more general way, with respect to their relation to some end, whether or not this increase or diminish their gravity.[12] Thus, these classifications must be seen as different modes of examining lies which complement each other.

Footnotes 

[1] St. Augustine, “On Lying,” c25. I have added here elements which Lombard himself cut out from his quotation, to put the whole of Augustine’s statement in context.
[2] Ibid., c42.
[3] Rufinus of Aquileia, Historia monachorum, De Iohanne I, bk I, c 2, n5 in Peter Lombard, Sentences. Book III, dist XXXVIII, c2.
[4] Which, obviously is the case with the beast of revelation, “Men worshiped the dragon, for he had given his authority to the beast, and they worshiped the beast, saying, ‘Who is like the beast, and who can fight against it?’ And the beast was given a mouth uttering haughty and blasphemous words, and it was allowed to exercise authority for forty-two months; it opened its mouth to utter blasphemies against God, blaspheming his name and his dwelling, that is, those who dwell in heaven” (Rev.13:4-6).
[5] If they suggest some other reason, such as “paying” someone back, then the lie differs from what is presented here, because some sense of justice, a good, is being employed.
[6] The person who gains does not have to be the liar themselves. For example, let’s take three people, Jack, Jill, and Mary. All three are involved with politics. Both Jill and Mary are running for office, and Jack is Mary’s campaign advisor. If Mary were put into office, she would be of more positive help than Jill, though it would be hard to prove this by her record. Jack hates Jill, and wants to destroy her political career; he finds a way which allows him to lie about Jill, to destroy her political career, and does it, helping Mary get into office. While Mary’s new position is an actual good, the malice involved in Jack’s lie would undermine the good he accomplished in getting her into office. Now this is the kind of harm Augustine intends when he says that the harm involved is to be non-corporal; but what are we to say of a lie which leads to bodily harm? Augustine does not answer, but one could suggest that he thinks a far greater sin is involved, and that sin is what needs to be addressed, not the lie, but if one were to address the lie, it would have to lie somewhere between the second and third kinds, because there is still some positive good intended by the act. Lombard, on the other hand, does not mention corporal defilement when quoting from Augustine, simplifying the matter.
[7] This is how St Thomas Aquinas understands Augustine, as can be found in ST  II-II, Q110, Art2.
[8] Of the elimination of habits, St Thomas Aquinas says, “Consequently all habits that are gradually undermined by contrary agencies which need to be counteracted by acts proceeding from those habits, are diminished or even destroyed altogether by long cessation from act, as is clearly seen in the case both of science and of virtue. For it is evident that a habit of moral virtue makes a man ready to choose the mean in deeds and passions. And when a man fails to make use of his virtuous habit in order to moderate his own passions or deeds, the necessary result is that many passions and deeds fail to observe the mode of virtue, by reason of the inclination of the sensitive appetite and of other external agencies. Wherefore virtue is destroyed or lessened through cessation from act,” St Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica. Trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1948), II-I, Q53, Art3.
[9] Thus, as St Thomas Aquinas says, “Now it is evident that the greater the good intended, the more is the sin of lying diminished in gravity.” Ibid., II-II, Q110, Art2.
[10] In the fictional The Princess Bride, we have an example of what this might be like: Wesley threatens Humperdink with “the pain,” a humiliating position where he loses his limbs, his tongue, his eyes, but is left with his ears so he could hear the cries of horror from those around him, “That is what ‘to the pain’ means. It means that I leave you in anguish, in humiliation, in freakish misery until you can stand no more…” William Goldman, The Princess Bride: 25th Anniversary Edition. (New York: Ballantine Books, 1998), 312. In this way, the physical harm intends such a desecration of the subject, they would despair of life itself, and protecting someone from this kind of harm would be to protect them from sin.
[11] ST II-II, Q110, Art2.
[12] ST II-II, Q110, Art2.


Browse Our Archives